<
Texts on topics |
cikon.de | pdf, 85 KB |
The Mind-Body Problem – is it Really a Problem?
What is the problem supposed to be and what would qualify as a solution? To begin with let us speculate on how this alleged problem came about in the first place. Presumably it came about because some people noted an undeniable big difference between a rock and themselves. They also noted differences between themselves and what they perceived as other forms of life: of plants and all animals other than humans.
These differences mainly become manifest in what humans can do that rocks, plants and non-human animals cannot do. Humans can talk, they can set up vast intra-species communication networks, and – above all - they can create symbolic worlds that empower them to transform their environments and define the relations among themselves in unprecedented ways.
In addition, humans have, by their own accounts (that can be – within limits – symbolically communicated via spoken and/or body language), rich inner experiences (as opposed to experiences directly triggered by external sensory input) leading them to believe in being indivisible, unique “selfs” (yet another inner experience) and normally to count on fellow humans to be capable of the same or similar experiences. (But they do not normally count on non-human biological entities to be capable of the same or similar experiences.)
So they conclude that there is indeed something special about them, that they have been endowed with faculties no other material / physical entity has been endowed with. They believe these faculties are brought about by something they call “mind” and many are convinced that there must be a categorical difference between the mental and the physical.
One may assume that in our post-Darwinian era we do not need either ghosts or a deus ex machina (or ex whatever else) to explain the presence of this something in (or outside?) our bodies and somehow controlling the way our bodies behave. Indeed, apart from (a not so few) diehards, within scientific communities it now appears to be generally received wisdom not to postulate an external being that somehow imbues our bodies with some sort of mysterious spirit. And not to invent fairy-tale stories dressed up in lofty philosophical terms that do not explain (by any standard) anything, but at best obscure what ought to be explained (dualism, monism, physicalism, materialism, eliminativism, etc., etc.).
So what is the problem? Is it: what leads to the development within an embodied material / physical system, of the above mentioned faculties? Or, in slightly more elaborate parlance: what makes a material system develop internal structures and mappings of its environment into these structures, so that the ensuing internal dynamics make it exhibit said mental faculties?
Problem solved? Or problem dissolved? Yes and no. Nature or, rather, its terrestrial biosphere subsystem (largely based on the elements C, H, N, O, P, and S) certainly has (or had?) the tools and building blocks that sufficed to evolve mentally endowed bodies. But are they necessary? “If biosphere then mind is possible.” is true (we are living proof of this statement). Is the reverse also true: “If mind then only in a biosphere”? In other words: “The terrestrial biosphere can bring forth mentally endowed bodies.” But: “Does bringing forth mentally endowed bodies require a biosphere of the earthly type? Is a terrestrial biosphere a necessary and sufficient prerequisite for creating mentally endowed bodies? Is CHNOPS-’technology’ the only way or are other ways possible?” This is indeed an unsolved problem. Or is it? We shall come back to it.
Of course, apart from creating mentally endowed bodies on Earth (i.e., solving our mind-body problem), Nature has found constructive solutions to a host of other problems (not posed by us or anybody). For instance to the problem of producing solar systems in the first place, providing inter alia the conditions for the emergence of biospheres. Many of the problems Nature has solved, keep scores of physicists busy. They try to decipher Nature’s ways and to convey their insights in terms of mathematically phrased Laws of Nature.
They figure out these laws by collecting data through observation, experiment, and measurement, and by theory building based on these data and their own ingenuity. Sometimes also through learned guessing and divining a theory. However they do it, they have to corroborate their theories by deriving predictions which can either be confirmed or falsified through observation, experiment and measurement. A theory is successful as long as its predictions are not proven wrong (i.e. falsified). Theory building necessarily involves abstractions, called models, of the particular aspects of physical reality (i.e., Nature’s solutions) that are being studied.
But even if physicists have managed to create an (at least temporarily) successful theory, what have they actually understood? What does it mean to understand Nature’s solutions? To describe in intelligible terms the way they came about and the way they work (e.g., Big Bang, inflationary universe and formation of galaxies)? Perhaps.
The best we can hope for – given the limitations of our mental faculties - is to find out what minds do and how they do what they do. We have a pretty good idea of how minds came about. Certain mental faculties seem to have given some animals a big comparative advantage over other animals. The rest is evolution. We also have a pretty good idea of what internal body structures imply these mental faculties. There is little doubt that the key components are the brain, with its (over time) increasingly complex neural networks, and the sensory organs connected to it. One may add all sorts of glands whose products have a modulating influence on neural processes in the brain. And other parts of the body are of course also involved, somehow. All in all a matter of evolution.
It should by now be clear that when we say “mind” we actually mean the totality of mental faculties that allow animals (including humans) to act in their respective environments in non-arbitrary ways. And by mental faculty we mean the ability of a body to map (aspects of) its environment into its internal structures and to process the results of these mappings within its internal structures, often leading to observable behaviour. Studying this totality has always been within the domain of psychology (for humans) and ethology (for all other animals). Traditionally, however, both focus mainly on behaviour rather than the underlying internal processes. Their concern is mainly with what the mind does rather than with how it works. (Or, to put it in terms of currently popular metaphors: They are more interested in the set of functions of the system than in the algorithms inside the system that compute these functions.)
And as in the above discussed case of physics, an indication of our understanding the brain and how it works (Nature’s solution of the mind-body problem!), may be the ability to put this knowledge to some use, for instance to building systems, perhaps machines, Nature has not provided so far. Here we deliberately chose almost the same wording as above. We also repeat the question: ”Is CHNOPS-’technology’ the only way (to create mentally endowed bodies) or are other ways possible?”
The answer is once again “yes and no”. It depends on whether or not we limit the scope of the term ”mind” to members of the species Homo Sapiens. If we do then by definition we are the only ”mentally endowed bodies”, and only CHNOPS-’technology’ can produce us. This of course also holds upon extending the scope of the term to the animal kingdom. But whether Homo Sapiens can fully understand Nature’s solution in terms of replicating it through artifacts that are mentally indistinguishable from the typical human mind is an entirely different question.
Moreover, if we want to achieve an emulation of the human mind (i.e., brain!) that is successful in the sense of being indistinguishable from the original then we would have to ask, for example: What does self-awareness of an embodied physical system mean? To perceive itself as separate from its environment, to form an internal representation of itself? How can it be tested? In what behavioural traits (or stimulus-response patterns and processes) does self-awareness - experiencing oneself as a subject, as a being with understanding, beliefs and volition - manifest itself? What are inner experiences, technically? Are “zombies” a theoretical and practical possibility?
1It should be noted that some philosophers and scientists wonder if something they call downward or top-down causation - a force or impulse emanating from some hypothetical high level (the mental) - plays a major role in making us think, move, talk, employ our physical strength, et cetera (http://humbleapproach.templeton.org/Top_Down_Causation/). However, as far as Nature is concerned, the level metaphor, a man-made abstraction, is misleading at best. It may denote stages of aggregation of (elementary) parts, controlled by principles, features and forces inherent in these parts, and subject to whatever environmental initial and boundary conditions that may be relevant. Obviously, aggregation results in entities (aggregates) that are different from their parts but with features and dynamics determined by their parts. Causation at the aggregate level then comes down to the impact the very process of aggregation and its outcome have on the parts involved.
2http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24266-scientific-understanding-philosophical-perspectives/
3https://www.britannica.com/topic/noumenon
4Hence mental activities (including vision, language production and understanding, thinking, etc.) are identical to neural processes, characterised by the firing of neurons within and across brain regions. The technical metaphor together with this identity may indeed help to understand why mental activities cause behaviour. Technically, abstracting from everything else, neurons are like switches. Flipping a switch is a low-energy event that can trigger and control high(er)-energy phenomena. In this regard a neuron in the brain is very much like a transistor in an amplifier or a transistor in a computer that - upon some external event - turns on an alarm.
5It is, by the way, common knowledge and requires no sophisticated theory to explain that consuming certain drugs and other substances, by altering the mind (i.e., electrochemical processes in the brain), can have a dramatic and - to a certain extent - predictable effect not only on observable behaviour but also on an individual’s inner experience.
6As Anil Seth, a computational neuroscientist at the University of Sussex, in an op-ed article in The Guardian, pointed out: even if more detailed simulations of the brain could be achieved this would "not inevitably lead to better understanding. Strikingly, we don’t fully understand the brain of the tiny worm Caenorhabditis elegans even though it has only 302 neurons and the wiring diagram is known exactly. A perfectly accurate model of the brain may become as difficult to understand as the brain itself, as Jorge Luis Borges long ago noted when describing the tragic uselessness of the perfectly detailed map."
7http://www.humanconnectomeproject.org/
8https://www.humanbrainproject.eu/
9https://www.wikiwand.com/en/Neuromorphic_engineering
10That is of course also true, mutatis mutandis, of dog-minds, cat-minds, elephant-minds, monkey-minds, et cetera.
11Well, there may be some self-referentiality: in a way it is Nature herself who is posing a problem to herself in the form of one of her solutions (the human “mind”): How did I do it (the human “mind”) and how does it work? This problem becomes indeed part of the solution.